1. トップ
  2. ブログ・お知らせ
ブログ・お知らせ

e-8

2018.12.31

Many of us can conceive of penalties that seem disproportionate to the crimes they are intended to punish. A sentence of probation for a person convicted of a brutal murder is one example of such an imbalance. At the other extreme is a sentence of twenty years in prison for shoplifting. But what is the source of these commonsense intuitions about the appropriateness of punishments? There are two main rationales(根拠と訳したほうがいいか)for punishing criminals. The first rationale justifies a punishment in terms of its benefit to society. Society is said to benefit whenever the fear of punishment deters a person from committing a crime, or when a convicted criminal is removed from contact with society at large. The second rationale is that a punishment is justified by the severity of the crime, independent of any benefit to society. This rationale is controversial because some find it difficult to see how a punishment can be justified if it brings no societal benefit: without such benefit, punishment would appear to be little more than retribution. But from the retributivist point of view, the question to be asked about punishment is not whether it is beneficial, but whether it is just―that is, appropriate. One problem with the social-benefit rationale is that it is possible that very harsh penalties even for minor offenses may have great benefit to society. For example, if shoplifters faced twenty-year jail sentences, shoplifting might be deterred. Yet something leads us to say that in such cases the penalty far outweighs the crime. That is, there appears to be something intuitively wrong, or unjust, about these punishments. And it would seem that this intuition can only find support in a retributive conception of punishment, under which certain types of punishments are inherently more appropriate than others. The notion of appropriateness is absent from the first rationale, which could conceivably allow for any sort of punishment as long as it benefits society. Retributive considerations, on the other hand, allow for proportionality between punishments and crimes. This is what fuels our notion of just (as opposed to beneficial) punishment. However, it can be argued that our intuition of the injustice of an overly harsh punishment is based on our sense that such a punishment is more harmful to the criminal than beneficial to society: and, similarly, that our intuition that a punishment is just is based on our sense that this punishment fairly balances societal benefit against harm to the criminal. In this way the second rationale can be seen as grounded in the first and its retributive nature disappears. Thus it seems that even our so-called intuitive notions of the appropriateness of punishments have their basis in the concept of benefit.

the first rational(処罰の根拠一つ目) = 社会にとってプラス the second rationale(処罰の根拠二つ目) = 処罰の正しさ 文章の最初の箇所ではこの二つは別個と説明していましたが、論理の展開でthe second rationaleはthe first rational(社会にとってプラス) と無関係ではなく、それとのバランスの中で決まってくる、と変わっています。したがって、報復では決してない、というのが作者の結論でしょうね。 However, it can be argued 1(that our intuition of the injustice of an overly harsh punishment is based on our sense that such a punishment is more harmful to the criminal than beneficial to society): and, similarly, 2(that our intuition that a punishment is just is based on our sense that this punishment fairly balances societal benefit against harm to the criminal.)

総合英語塾ブログ・お知らせ

学習スタイル

テキスト&解説

合格体験記

お問い合わせ

E-mail
fgifgi@hotmail.com

■返信が届かないお客様へ

当英語塾は遅くとも2日以内にお問い合わせに対する返事のメールを差し上げています。
もし、2日以内に当英語塾から連絡がない場合は、メールの受信がうまく行えていない可能性が大です。
その際は、大変お手数ではございますが、お電話にてお問合せください。